Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 82 [<< | >>]
We must now consider original sin as to its essence, and under this head
there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether original sin is a habit?
(2) Whether there is but one original sin in each man?
(3) Whether original sin is concupiscence?
(4) Whether original sin is equally in all?
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 82 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that original sin is not a habit. For original sin
is the absence of original justice, as Anselm states (De Concep. Virg.
ii, iii, xxvi), so that original sin is a privation. But privation is
opposed to habit. Therefore original sin is not a habit.
Objection 2: Further, actual sin has the nature of fault more than original
sin, in so far as it is more voluntary. Now the habit of actual sin has
not the nature of a fault, else it would follow that a man while asleep,
would be guilty of sin. Therefore no original habit has the nature of a
fault.
Objection 3: Further, in wickedness act always precedes habit, because evil
habits are not infused, but acquired. Now original sin is not preceded by
an act. Therefore original sin is not a habit.
On the contrary, Augustine says in his book on the Baptism of infants
(De Pecc. Merit. et Remiss. i, 39) that on account of original sin little
children have the aptitude of concupiscence though they have not the act.
Now aptitude denotes some kind of habit. Therefore original sin is a
habit.
I answer that, As stated above (Question [49], Article [4]; Question [50], Article [1]), habit is
twofold. The first is a habit whereby power is inclined to an act: thus
science and virtue are called habits. In this way original sin is not a
habit. The second kind of habit is the disposition of a complex nature,
whereby that nature is well or ill disposed to something, chiefly when
such a disposition has become like a second nature, as in the case of
sickness or health. In this sense original sin is a habit. For it is an
inordinate disposition, arising from the destruction of the harmony which
was essential to original justice, even as bodily sickness is an
inordinate disposition of the body, by reason of the destruction of that
equilibrium which is essential to health. Hence it is that original sin
is called the "languor of nature" [*Cf. Augustine, In Ps. 118, serm. iii].
Reply to Objection 1: As bodily sickness is partly a privation, in so far as it
denotes the destruction of the equilibrium of health, and partly
something positive, viz. the very humors that are inordinately disposed,
so too original sin denotes the privation of original justice, and
besides this, the inordinate disposition of the parts of the soul.
Consequently it is not a pure privation, but a corrupt habit.
Reply to Objection 2: Actual sin is an inordinateness of an act: whereas original
sin, being the sin of nature, is an inordinate disposition of nature, and
has the character of fault through being transmitted from our first
parent, as stated above (Question [81], Article [1]). Now this inordinate disposition of
nature is a kind of habit, whereas the inordinate disposition of an act
is not: and for this reason original sin can be a habit, whereas actual
sin cannot.
Reply to Objection 3: This objection considers the habit which inclines a power
to an act: but original sin is not this kind of habit. Nevertheless a
certain inclination to an inordinate act does follow from original sin,
not directly, but indirectly, viz. by the removal of the obstacle, i.e.
original justice, which hindered inordinate movements: just as an
inclination to inordinate bodily movements results indirectly from bodily
sickness. Nor is it necessary to says that original sin is a habit
"infused," or a habit "acquired" (except by the act of our first parent,
but not by our own act): but it is a habit "inborn" due to our corrupt
origin.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 82 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that there are many original sins in one man. For
it is written (@Ps. 1:7): "Behold I was conceived in iniquities, and in
sins did my mother conceive me." But the sin in which a man is conceived
is original sin. Therefore there are several original sins in man.
Objection 2: Further, one and the same habit does not incline its subject to
contraries: since the inclination of habit is like that of nature which
tends to one thing. Now original sin, even in one man, inclines to
various and contrary sins. Therefore original sin is not one habit; but
several.
Objection 3: Further, original sin infects every part of the soul. Now the
different parts of the soul are different subjects of sin, as shown above
(Question [74]). Since then one sin cannot be in different subjects, it seems
that original sin is not one but several.
On the contrary, It is written (@Jn. 1:29): "Behold the Lamb of God,
behold Him Who taketh away the sin of the world": and the reason for the
employment of the singular is that the "sin of the world" is original
sin, as a gloss expounds this passage.
I answer that, In one man there is one original sin. Two reasons may be
assigned for this. The first is on the part of the cause of original sin.
For it has been stated (Question [81], Article [2]), that the first sin alone of our
first parent was transmitted to his posterity. Wherefore in one man
original sin is one in number; and in all men, it is one in proportion,
i.e. in relation to its first principle. The second reason may be taken
from the very essence of original sin. Because in every inordinate
disposition, unity of species depends on the cause, while the unity of
number is derived from the subject. For example, take bodily sickness:
various species of sickness proceed from different causes, e.g. from
excessive heat or cold, or from a lesion in the lung or liver; while one
specific sickness in one man will be one in number. Now the cause of this
corrupt disposition that is called original sin, is one only, viz. the
privation of original justice, removing the subjection of man's mind to
God. Consequently original sin is specifically one, and, in one man, can
be only one in number; while, in different men, it is one in species and
in proportion, but is numerically many.
Reply to Objection 1: The employment of the plural---"in sins"---may be explained
by the custom of the Divine Scriptures in the frequent use of the plural
for the singular, e.g. "They are dead that sought the life of the child";
or by the fact that all actual sins virtually pre-exist in original sin,
as in a principle so that it is virtually many; or by the fact of there
being many deformities in the sin of our first parent, viz. pride,
disobedience, gluttony, and so forth; or by several parts of the soul
being infected by original sin.
Reply to Objection 2: Of itself and directly, i.e. by its own form, one habit
cannot incline its subject to contraries. But there is no reason why it
should not do so, indirectly and accidentally, i.e. by the removal of an
obstacle: thus, when the harmony of a mixed body is destroyed, the
elements have contrary local tendencies. In like manner, when the harmony
of original justice is destroyed, the various powers of the soul have
various opposite tendencies.
Reply to Objection 3: Original sin infects the different parts of the soul, in so
far as they are the parts of one whole; even as original justice held all
the soul's parts together in one. Consequently there is but one original
sin: just as there is but one fever in one man, although the various
parts of the body are affected.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 82 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that original sin is not concupiscence. For every
sin is contrary to nature, according to Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii,
4,30). But concupiscence is in accordance with nature, since it is the
proper act of the concupiscible faculty which is a natural power.
Therefore concupiscence is not original sin.
Objection 2: Further, through original sin "the passions of sins" are in us,
according to the Apostle (@Rm. 7:5). Now there are several other passions
besides concupiscence, as stated above (Question [23], Article [4]). Therefore original
sin is not concupiscence any more than another passion.
Objection 3: Further, by original sin, all the parts of the soul are
disordered, as stated above (Article [2], Objection [3]). But the intellect is the
highest of the soul's parts, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. x, 7).
Therefore original sin is ignorance rather than concupiscence.
On the contrary, Augustine says (Retract. i, 15): "Concupiscence is the
guilt of original sin."
I answer that, Everything takes its species from its form: and it has
been stated (Article [2]) that the species of original sin is taken from its
cause. Consequently the formal element of original sin must be considered
in respect of the cause of original sin. But contraries have contrary
causes. Therefore the cause of original sin must be considered with
respect to the cause of original justice, which is opposed to it. Now the
whole order of original justice consists in man's will being subject to
God: which subjection, first and chiefly, was in the will, whose function
it is to move all the other parts to the end, as stated above (Question [9], Article [1]), so that the will being turned away from God, all the other powers of
the soul become inordinate. Accordingly the privation of original
justice, whereby the will was made subject to God, is the formal element
in original sin; while every other disorder of the soul's powers, is a
kind of material element in respect of original sin. Now the
inordinateness of the other powers of the soul consists chiefly in their
turning inordinately to mutable good; which inordinateness may be called
by the general name of concupiscence. Hence original sin is
concupiscence, materially, but privation of original justice, formally.
Reply to Objection 1: Since, in man, the concupiscible power is naturally
governed by reason, the act of concupiscence is so far natural to man, as
it is in accord with the order of reason; while, in so far as it
trespasses beyond the bounds of reason, it is, for a man, contrary to
reason. Such is the concupiscence of original sin.
Reply to Objection 2: As stated above (Question [25], Article [1]), all the irascible passions
are reducible to concupiscible passions, as holding the principle place:
and of these, concupiscence is the most impetuous in moving, and is felt
most, as stated above (Question [25], Article [2], ad 1). Therefore original sin is
ascribed to concupiscence, as being the chief passion, and as including
all the others, in a fashion.
Reply to Objection 3: As, in good things, the intellect and reason stand first,
so conversely in evil things, the lower part of the soul is found to take
precedence, for it clouds and draws the reason, as stated above (Question [77], Articles [1],2; Question [80], Article [2]). Hence original sin is called concupiscence rather
than ignorance, although ignorance is comprised among the material
defects of original sin.
Index [<< | >>]
First Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 82 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that original sin is not equally in all. Because
original sin is inordinate concupiscence, as stated above (Article [3]). Now all
are not equally prone to acts of concupiscence. Therefore original sin is
not equally in all.
Objection 2: Further, original sin is an inordinate disposition of the soul,
just as sickness is an inordinate disposition of the body. But sickness
is subject to degrees. Therefore original sin is subject to degrees.
Objection 3: Further, Augustine says (De Nup. et Concep. i, 23) that "lust
transmits original sin to the child." But the act of generation may be
more lustful in one than in another. Therefore original sin may be
greater in one than in another.
On the contrary, Original sin is the sin of nature, as stated above
(Question [81], Article [1]). But nature is equally in all. Therefore original sin is
too.
I answer that, There are two things in original sin: one is the
privation of original justice; the other is the relation of this
privation to the sin of our first parent, from whom it is transmitted to
man through his corrupt origin. As to the first, original sin has no
degrees, since the gift of original justice is taken away entirely; and
privations that remove something entirely, such as death and darkness,
cannot be more or less, as stated above (Question [73], Article [2]). In like manner,
neither is this possible, as to the second: since all are related equally
to the first principle of our corrupt origin, from which principle
original sin takes the nature of guilt; for relations cannot be more or
less. Consequently it is evident that original sin cannot be more in one
than in another.
Reply to Objection 1: Through the bond of original justice being broken, which
held together all the powers of the soul in a certain order, each power
of the soul tends to its own proper movement, and the more impetuously,
as it is stronger. Now it happens that some of the soul's powers are
stronger in one man than in another, on account of the different bodily
temperaments. Consequently if one man is more prone than another to acts
of concupiscence, this is not due to original sin, because the bond of
original justice is equally broken in all, and the lower parts of the
soul are, in all, left to themselves equally; but it is due to the
various dispositions of the powers, as stated.
Reply to Objection 2: Sickness of the body, even sickness of the same species,
has not an equal cause in all; for instance if a fever be caused by
corruption of the bile, the corruption may be greater or less, and nearer
to, or further from a vital principle. But the cause of original sin is
equal to all, so that there is not comparison.
Reply to Objection 3: It is not the actual lust that transmits original sin: for,
supposing God were to grant to a man to feel no inordinate lust in the
act of generation, he would still transmit original sin; we must
understand this to be habitual lust, whereby the sensitive appetite is
not kept subject to reason by the bonds of original justice. This lust is
equally in all.