Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
In due sequence we must consider judgment, under which head there are
six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether judgment is an act of justice?
(2) Whether it is lawful to judge?
(3) Whether judgment should be based on suspicions?
(4) Whether doubts should be interpreted favorably?
(5) Whether judgment should always be given according to the written law?
(6) Whether judgment is perverted by being usurped?
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that judgment is not an act of justice. The
Philosopher says (Ethic. i, 3) that "everyone judges well of what he
knows," so that judgment would seem to belong to the cognitive faculty.
Now the cognitive faculty is perfected by prudence. Therefore judgment
belongs to prudence rather than to justice, which is in the will, as
stated above (Question [58], Article [4]).
Objection 2: Further, the Apostle says (@1 Cor. 2:15): "The spiritual man
judgeth all things." Now man is made spiritual chiefly by the virtue of
charity, which "is poured forth in our hearts by the Holy Ghost Who is
given to us" (@Rm. 5:5). Therefore judgment belongs to charity rather than
to justice.
Objection 3: Further, it belongs to every virtue to judge aright of its proper
matter, because "the virtuous man is the rule and measure in everything,"
according to the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 4). Therefore judgment does not
belong to justice any more than to the other moral virtues.
Objection 4: Further, judgment would seem to belong only to judges. But the
act of justice is to be found in every just man. Since then judges are
not the only just men, it seems that judgment is not the proper act of
justice.
On the contrary, It is written (@Ps. 93:15): "Until justice be turned
into judgment."
I answer that, Judgment properly denotes the act of a judge as such. Now
a judge [judex] is so called because he asserts the right [jus dicens]
and right is the object of justice, as stated above (Question [57], Article [1]).
Consequently the original meaning of the word "judgment" is a statement
or decision of the just or right. Now to decide rightly about virtuous
deeds proceeds, properly speaking, from the virtuous habit; thus a chaste
person decides rightly about matters relating to chastity. Therefore
judgment, which denotes a right decision about what is just, belongs
properly to justice. For this reason the Philosopher says (Ethic. v, 4)
that "men have recourse to a judge as to one who is the personification
of justice."
Reply to Objection 1: The word "judgment," from its original meaning of a right
decision about what is just, has been extended to signify a right
decision in any matter whether speculative or practical. Now a right
judgment in any matter requires two things. The first is the virtue
itself that pronounces judgment: and in this way, judgment is an act of
reason, because it belongs to the reason to pronounce or define. The
other is the disposition of the one who judges, on which depends his
aptness for judging aright. In this way, in matters of justice, judgment
proceeds from justice, even as in matters of fortitude, it proceeds from
fortitude. Accordingly judgment is an act of justice in so far as justice
inclines one to judge aright, and of prudence in so far as prudence
pronounces judgment: wherefore {synesis} (judging well according to
common law) which belongs to prudence is said to "judge rightly," as
stated above (Question [51], Article [3]).
Reply to Objection 2: The spiritual man, by reason of the habit of charity, has
an inclination to judge aright of all things according to the Divine
rules; and it is in conformity with these that he pronounces judgment
through the gift of wisdom: even as the just man pronounces judgment
through the virtue of prudence conformably with the ruling of the law.
Reply to Objection 3: The other virtues regulate man in himself, whereas justice
regulates man in his dealings with others, as shown above (Question [58], Article [2]).
Now man is master in things concerning himself, but not in matters
relating to others. Consequently where the other virtues are in question,
there is no need for judgment other than that of a virtuous man, taking
judgment in its broader sense, as explained above (ad 1). But in matters
of justice, there is further need for the judgment of a superior, who is
"able to reprove both, and to put his hand between both" [*Job 9:33].
Hence judgment belongs more specifically to justice than to any other
virtue.
Reply to Objection 4: Justice is in the sovereign as a master-virtue [*Cf. Question [58],
Article [6]], commanding and prescribing what is just; while it is in the
subjects as an executive and administrative virtue. Hence judgment, which
denotes a decision of what is just, belongs to justice, considered as
existing chiefly in one who has authority.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem unlawful to judge. For nothing is punished except
what is unlawful. Now those who judge are threatened with punishment,
which those who judge not will escape, according to Mt. 7:1, "Judge not,
and ye shall not be judged." Therefore it is unlawful to judge.
Objection 2: Further, it is written (@Rm. 14:4): "Who art thou that judgest
another man's servant. To his own lord he standeth or falleth." Now God
is the Lord of all. Therefore to no man is it lawful to judge.
Objection 3: Further, no man is sinless, according to 1 Jn. 1:8, "If we say
that we have no sin, we deceive ourselves." Now it is unlawful for a
sinner to judge, according to Rm. 2:1, "Thou art inexcusable, O man,
whosoever thou art, that judgest; for wherein thou judgest another, thou
condemnest thyself, for thou dost the same things which thou judgest."
Therefore to no man is it lawful to judge.
On the contrary, It is written (@Dt. 16:18): "Thou shalt appoint judges
and magistrates in all thy gates . . . that they may judge the people
with just judgment."
I answer that, Judgment is lawful in so far as it is an act of justice.
Now it follows from what has been stated above (Article [1], ad 1,3) that three
conditions are requisite for a judgment to be an act of justice: first,
that it proceed from the inclination of justice; secondly, that it come
from one who is in authority; thirdly, that it be pronounced according to
the right ruling of prudence. If any one of these be lacking, the
judgment will be faulty and unlawful. First, when it is contrary to the
rectitude of justice, and then it is called "perverted" or "unjust":
secondly, when a man judges about matters wherein he has no authority,
and this is called judgment "by usurpation": thirdly, when the reason
lacks certainty, as when a man, without any solid motive, forms a
judgment on some doubtful or hidden matter, and then it is called
judgment by "suspicion" or "rash" judgment.
Reply to Objection 1: In these words our Lord forbids rash judgment which is
about the inward intention, or other uncertain things, as Augustine
states (De Serm. Dom. in Monte ii, 18). Or else He forbids judgment about
Divine things, which we ought not to judge, but simply believe, since
they are above us, as Hilary declares in his commentary on Mt. 5. Or
again according to Chrysostom [*Hom. xvii in Matth. in the Opus
Imperfectum falsely ascribed to St. John of the Cross], He forbids the
judgment which proceeds not from benevolence but from bitterness of heart.
Reply to Objection 2: A judge is appointed as God's servant; wherefore it is written (@Dt. 1:16): "Judge that which is just," and further on (@Dt. 1:17), "because it is the judgment of God."
Reply to Objection 3: Those who stand guilty of grievous sins should not judge
those who are guilty of the same or lesser sins, as Chrysostom [*Hom.
xxiv] says on the words of Mt. 7:1, "Judge not." Above all does this hold
when such sins are public, because there would be an occasion of scandal
arising in the hearts of others. If however they are not public but
hidden, and there be an urgent necessity for the judge to pronounce
judgment, because it is his duty, he can reprove or judge with humility
and fear. Hence Augustine says (De Serm. Dom. in Monte ii, 19): "If we
find that we are guilty of the same sin as another man, we should groan
together with him, and invite him to strive against it together with us."
And yet it is not through acting thus that a man condemns himself so as
to deserve to be condemned once again, but when, in condemning another,
he shows himself to be equally deserving of condemnation on account of
another or a like sin.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that it is not unlawful to form a judgment from
suspicions. For suspicion is seemingly an uncertain opinion about an
evil, wherefore the Philosopher states (Ethic. vi, 3) that suspicion is
about both the true and the false. Now it is impossible to have any but
an uncertain opinion about contingent singulars. Since then human
judgment is about human acts, which are about singular and contingent
matters, it seems that no judgment would be lawful, if it were not lawful
to judge from suspicions.
Objection 2: Further, a man does his neighbor an injury by judging him
unlawfully. But an evil suspicion consists in nothing more than a man's
opinion, and consequently does not seem to pertain to the injury of
another man. Therefore judgment based on suspicion is not unlawful.
Objection 3: Further, if it is unlawful, it must needs be reducible to an
injustice, since judgment is an act of justice, as stated above (Article [1]).
Now an injustice is always a mortal sin according to its genus, as stated
above (Question [59], Article [4]). Therefore a judgment based on suspicion would always
be a mortal sin, if it were unlawful. But this is false, because "we
cannot avoid suspicions," according to a gloss of Augustine (Tract. xc in
Joan.) on 1 Cor. 4:5, "Judge not before the time." Therefore a judgment
based on suspicion would seem not to be unlawful.
On the contrary, Chrysostom [*Hom. xvii in Matth. in the Opus
Imperfectum falsely ascribed to St. John of the Cross] in comment on the
words of Mt. 7:1, "Judge not," etc., says: "By this commandment our Lord
does not forbid Christians to reprove others from kindly motives, but
that Christian should despise Christian by boasting his own
righteousness, by hating and condemning others for the most part on mere
suspicion."
I answer that, As Tully says (De Invent. Rhet. ii), suspicion denotes
evil thinking based on slight indications, and this is due to three
causes. First, from a man being evil in himself, and from this very fact,
as though conscious of his own wickedness, he is prone to think evil of
others, according to Eccles. 10:3, "The fool when he walketh in the way,
whereas he himself is a fool, esteemeth all men fools." Secondly, this is
due to a man being ill-disposed towards another: for when a man hates or
despises another, or is angry with or envious of him, he is led by slight
indications to think evil of him, because everyone easily believes what
he desires. Thirdly, this is due to long experience: wherefore the
Philosopher says (Rhet. ii, 13) that "old people are very suspicious, for
they have often experienced the faults of others." The first two causes
of suspicion evidently connote perversity of the affections, while the
third diminishes the nature of suspicion, in as much as experience leads
to certainty which is contrary to the nature of suspicion. Consequently
suspicion denotes a certain amount of vice, and the further it goes, the
more vicious it is.
Now there are three degrees of suspicion. The first degree is when a man
begins to doubt of another's goodness from slight indications. This is a
venial and a light sin; for "it belongs to human temptation without which
no man can go through this life," according to a gloss on 1 Cor. 4:5,
"Judge not before the time." The second degree is when a man, from slight
indications, esteems another man's wickedness as certain. This is a
mortal sin, if it be about a grave matter, since it cannot be without
contempt of one's neighbor. Hence the same gloss goes on to say: "If then
we cannot avoid suspicions, because we are human, we must nevertheless
restrain our judgment, and refrain from forming a definite and fixed
opinion." The third degree is when a judge goes so far as to condemn a
man on suspicion: this pertains directly to injustice, and consequently
is a mortal sin.
Reply to Objection 1: Some kind of certainty is found in human acts, not indeed
the certainty of a demonstration, but such as is befitting the matter in
point, for instance when a thing is proved by suitable witnesses.
Reply to Objection 2: From the very fact that a man thinks evil of another
without sufficient cause, he despises him unduly, and therefore does him
an injury.
Reply to Objection 3: Since justice and injustice are about external operations,
as stated above (Question [58], Articles [8],10,11; Question [59], Article [1], ad 3), the judgment of
suspicion pertains directly to injustice when it is betrayed by external
action, and then it is a mortal sin, as stated above. The internal
judgment pertains to justice, in so far as it is related to the external
judgment, even as the internal to the external act, for instance as
desire is related to fornication, or anger to murder.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that doubts should not be interpreted for the best.
Because we should judge from what happens for the most part. But it
happens for the most part that evil is done, since "the number of fools
is infinite" (@Eccles. 1:15), "for the imagination and thought of man's
heart are prone to evil from his youth" (@Gn. 8:21). Therefore doubts
should be interpreted for the worst rather than for the best.
Objection 2: Further, Augustine says (De Doctr. Christ. i, 27) that "he leads
a godly and just life who is sound in his estimate of things, and turns
neither to this side nor to that." Now he who interprets a doubtful point
for the best, turns to one side. Therefore this should not be done.
Objection 3: Further, man should love his neighbor as himself. Now with regard
to himself, a man should interpret doubtful matters for the worst,
according to Job 9:28, "I feared all my works." Therefore it seems that
doubtful matters affecting one's neighbor should be interpreted for the
worst.
On the contrary, A gloss on Rm. 14:3, "He that eateth not, let him not
judge him that eateth," says: "Doubts should be interpreted in the best
sense."
I answer that, As stated above (Article [3], ad 2), things from the very fact
that a man thinks ill of another without sufficient cause, he injures and
despises him. Now no man ought to despise or in any way injure another
man without urgent cause: and, consequently, unless we have evident
indications of a person's wickedness, we ought to deem him good, by
interpreting for the best whatever is doubtful about him.
Reply to Objection 1: He who interprets doubtful matters for the best, may happen
to be deceived more often than not; yet it is better to err frequently
through thinking well of a wicked man, than to err less frequently
through having an evil opinion of a good man, because in the latter case
an injury is inflicted, but not in the former.
Reply to Objection 2: It is one thing to judge of things and another to judge of
men. For when we judge of things, there is no question of the good or
evil of the thing about which we are judging, since it will take no harm
no matter what kind of judgment we form about it; but there is question
of the good of the person who judges, if he judge truly, and of his evil
if he judge falsely because "the true is the good of the intellect, and
the false is its evil," as stated in Ethic. vi, 2, wherefore everyone
should strive to make his judgment accord with things as they are. On the
other hand when we judge of men, the good and evil in our judgment is
considered chiefly on the part of the person about whom judgment is being
formed; for he is deemed worthy of honor from the very fact that he is
judged to be good, and deserving of contempt if he is judged to be evil.
For this reason we ought, in this kind of judgment, to aim at judging a
man good, unless there is evident proof of the contrary. And though we
may judge falsely, our judgment in thinking well of another pertains to
our good feeling and not to the evil of the intellect, even as neither
does it pertain to the intellect's perfection to know the truth of
contingent singulars in themselves.
Reply to Objection 3: One may interpret something for the worst or for the best
in two ways. First, by a kind of supposition; and thus, when we have to
apply a remedy to some evil, whether our own or another's, in order for
the remedy to be applied with greater certainty of a cure, it is
expedient to take the worst for granted, since if a remedy be efficacious
against a worse evil, much more is it efficacious against a lesser evil.
Secondly we may interpret something for the best or for the worst, by
deciding or determining, and in this case when judging of things we
should try to interpret each thing according as it is, and when judging
of persons, to interpret things for the best as stated above.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 5 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that we ought not always to judge according to the
written law. For we ought always to avoid judging unjustly. But written
laws sometimes contain injustice, according to Is. 10:1, "Woe to them
that make wicked laws, and when they write, write injustice." Therefore
we ought not always to judge according to the written law.
Objection 2: Further, judgment has to be formed about individual happenings.
But no written law can cover each and every individual happening, as the
Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, 10). Therefore it seems that we are not
always bound to judge according to the written law.
Objection 3: Further, a law is written in order that the lawgiver's intention
may be made clear. But it happens sometimes that even if the lawgiver
himself were present he would judge otherwise. Therefore we ought not
always to judge according to the written law.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Vera Relig. xxxi): "In these earthly
laws, though men judge about them when they are making them, when once
they are established and passed, the judges may judge no longer of them,
but according to them."
I answer that, As stated above (Article [1]), judgment is nothing else but a
decision or determination of what is just. Now a thing becomes just in
two ways: first by the very nature of the case, and this is called
"natural right," secondly by some agreement between men, and this is
called "positive right," as stated above (Question [57], Article [2]). Now laws are
written for the purpose of manifesting both these rights, but in
different ways. For the written law does indeed contain natural right,
but it does not establish it, for the latter derives its force, not from
the law but from nature: whereas the written law both contains positive
right, and establishes it by giving it force of authority.
Hence it is necessary to judge according to the written law, else
judgment would fall short either of the natural or of the positive right.
Reply to Objection 1: Just as the written law does not give force to the natural
right, so neither can it diminish or annul its force, because neither
can man's will change nature. Hence if the written law contains anything
contrary to the natural right, it is unjust and has no binding force. For
positive right has no place except where "it matters not," according to
the natural right, "whether a thing be done in one way or in another"; as
stated above (Question [57], Article [2], ad 2). Wherefore such documents are to be
called, not laws, but rather corruptions of law, as stated above (FS,
Question [95], Article [2]): and consequently judgment should not be delivered according
to them.
Reply to Objection 2: Even as unjust laws by their very nature are, either always
or for the most part, contrary to the natural right, so too laws that are
rightly established, fail in some cases, when if they were observed they
would be contrary to the natural right. Wherefore in such cases judgment
should be delivered, not according to the letter of the law, but
according to equity which the lawgiver has in view. Hence the jurist says
[*Digest. i, 3; De leg. senatusque consult. 25]: "By no reason of law, or
favor of equity, is it allowable for us to interpret harshly, and render
burdensome, those useful measures which have been enacted for the welfare
of man." In such cases even the lawgiver himself would decide otherwise;
and if he had foreseen the case, he might have provided for it by law.
This suffices for the Reply to the Third Objection.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 60 [<< | >>]
Article: 6 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that judgment is not rendered perverse by being
usurped. For justice is rectitude in matters of action. Now truth is not
impaired, no matter who tells it, but it may suffer from the person who
ought to accept it. Therefore again justice loses nothing, no matter who
declares what is just, and this is what is meant by judgment.
Objection 2: Further, it belongs to judgment to punish sins. Now it is related
to the praise of some that they punished sins without having authority
over those whom they punished; such as Moses in slaying the Egyptian (@Ex. 2:12), and Phinees the son of Eleazar in slaying Zambri the son of Salu
(@Num. 25:7-14), and "it was reputed to him unto justice" (@Ps. 105:31).
Therefore usurpation of judgment pertains not to injustice.
Objection 3: Further, spiritual power is distinct from temporal. Now prelates
having spiritual power sometimes interfere in matters concerning the
secular power. Therefore usurped judgment is not unlawful.
Objection 4: Further, even as the judge requires authority in order to judge aright, so also does he need justice and knowledge, as shown above (Article [1], ad 1,3; Article [2]). But a judgment is not described as unjust, if he who judges lacks the habit of justice or the knowledge of the law. Neither therefore is it always unjust to judge by usurpation, i.e. without authority.
On the contrary, It is written (@Rm. 14:4): "Who art thou that judgest
another man's servant?"
I answer that, Since judgment should be pronounced according to the
written law, as stated above (Article [5]), he that pronounces judgment,
interprets, in a way, the letter of the law, by applying it to some
particular case. Now since it belongs to the same authority to interpret
and to make a law, just as a law cannot be made save by public authority,
so neither can a judgment be pronounced except by public authority, which
extends over those who are subject to the community. Wherefore even as it
would be unjust for one man to force another to observe a law that was
not approved by public authority, so too it is unjust, if a man compels
another to submit to a judgment that is pronounced by other than the
public authority.
Reply to Objection 1: When the truth is declared there is no obligation to accept
it, and each one is free to receive it or not, as he wishes. On the other
hand judgment implies an obligation, wherefore it is unjust for anyone to
be judged by one who has no public authority.
Reply to Objection 2: Moses seems to have slain the Egyptian by authority
received as it were, by divine inspiration; this seems to follow from
Acts 7:24, 25, where it is said that "striking the Egyptian . . . he
thought that his brethren understood that God by his hand would save
Israel [Vulg.: 'them']." Or it may be replied that Moses slew the
Egyptian in order to defend the man who was unjustly attacked, without
himself exceeding the limits of a blameless defence. Wherefore Ambrose
says (De Offic. i, 36) that "whoever does not ward off a blow from a
fellow man when he can, is as much in fault as the striker"; and he
quotes the example of Moses. Again we may reply with Augustine (Questions. Exod.
qu. 2) [*Cf. Contra Faust. xxii, 70] that just as "the soil gives proof
of its fertility by producing useless herbs before the useful seeds have
grown, so this deed of Moses was sinful although it gave a sign of great
fertility," in so far, to wit, as it was a sign of the power whereby he
was to deliver his people.
With regard to Phinees the reply is that he did this out of zeal for God
by Divine inspiration; or because though not as yet high-priest, he was
nevertheless the high-priest's son, and this judgment was his concern as
of the other judges, to whom this was commanded [*Ex. 22:20; Lev. 20; Dt.
13,17].
Reply to Objection 3: The secular power is subject to the spiritual, even as the
body is subject to the soul. Consequently the judgment is not usurped if
the spiritual authority interferes in those temporal matters that are
subject to the spiritual authority or which have been committed to the
spiritual by the temporal authority.
Reply to Objection 4: The habits of knowledge and justice are perfections of the
individual, and consequently their absence does not make a judgment to be
usurped, as in the absence of public authority which gives a judgment its
coercive force.