Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 79 [<< | >>]
We must now consider the quasi-integral parts of justice, which are "to
do good," and "to decline from evil," and the opposite vices. Under this
head there are four points of inquiry:
(1) Whether these two are parts of justice?
(2) Whether transgression is a special sin?
(3) Whether omission is a special sin?
(4) Of the comparison between omission and transgression.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 79 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that to decline from evil and to do good are not
parts of justice. For it belongs to every virtue to perform a good deed
and to avoid an evil one. But parts do not exceed the whole. Therefore to
decline from evil and to do good should not be reckoned parts of justice,
which is a special kind of virtue.
Objection 2: Further, a gloss on Ps. 33:15, "Turn away from evil and do good,"
says: "The former," i.e. to turn away from evil, "avoids sin, the
latter," i.e. to do good, "deserves the life and the palm." But any part
of a virtue deserves the life and the palm. Therefore to decline from
evil is not a part of justice.
Objection 3: Further, things that are so related that one implies the other,
are not mutually distinct as parts of a whole. Now declining from evil is
implied in doing good: since no one does evil and good at the same time.
Therefore declining from evil and doing good are not parts of justice.
On the contrary, Augustine (De Correp. et Grat. i) declares that
"declining from evil and doing good" belong to the justice of the law.
I answer that, If we speak of good and evil in general, it belongs to
every virtue to do good and to avoid evil: and in this sense they cannot
be reckoned parts of justice, except justice be taken in the sense of
"all virtue" [*Cf. Question [58], Article [5]]. And yet even if justice be taken in this
sense it regards a certain special aspect of good; namely, the good as
due in respect of Divine or human law.
On the other hand justice considered as a special virtue regards good as
due to one's neighbor. And in this sense it belongs to special justice to
do good considered as due to one's neighbor, and to avoid the opposite
evil, that, namely, which is hurtful to one's neighbor; while it belongs
to general justice to do good in relation to the community or in relation
to God, and to avoid the opposite evil.
Now these two are said to be quasi-integral parts of general or of
special justice, because each is required for the perfect act of justice.
For it belongs to justice to establish equality in our relations with
others, as shown above (Question [58], Article [2]): and it pertains to the same cause
to establish and to preserve that which it has established. Now a person
establishes the equality of justice by doing good, i.e. by rendering to
another his due: and he preserves the already established equality of
justice by declining from evil, that is by inflicting no injury on his
neighbor.
Reply to Objection 1: Good and evil are here considered under a special aspect,
by which they are appropriated to justice. The reason why these two are
reckoned parts of justice under a special aspect of good and evil, while
they are not reckoned parts of any other moral virtue, is that the other
moral virtues are concerned with the passions wherein to do good is to
observe the mean, which is the same as to avoid the extremes as evils: so
that doing good and avoiding evil come to the same, with regard to the
other virtues. On the other hand justice is concerned with operations and
external things, wherein to establish equality is one thing, and not to
disturb the equality established is another.
Reply to Objection 2: To decline from evil, considered as a part of justice, does
not denote a pure negation, viz."not to do evil"; for this does not
deserve the palm, but only avoids the punishment. But it implies a
movement of the will in repudiating evil, as the very term "decline"
shows. This is meritorious; especially when a person resists against an
instigation to do evil.
Reply to Objection 3: Doing good is the completive act of justice, and the
principal part, so to speak, thereof. Declining from evil is a more
imperfect act, and a secondary part of that virtue. Hence it is a.
material part, so to speak, thereof, and a necessary condition of the
formal and completive part.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 79 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that transgression is not a special sin. For no
species is included in the definition of its genus. Now transgression is
included in the definition of sin; because Ambrose says (De Parad. viii)
that sin is "a transgression of the Divine law." Therefore transgression
is not a species of sin.
Objection 2: Further, no species is more comprehensive than its genus. But
transgression is more comprehensive than sin, because sin is a "word,
deed or desire against the law of God," according to Augustine (Contra
Faust. xxii, 27), while transgression is also against nature, or custom.
Therefore transgression is not a species of sin.
Objection 3: Further, no species contains all the parts into which its genus
is divided. Now the sin of transgression extends to all the capital
vices, as well as to sins of thought, word and deed. Therefore
transgression is not a special sin.
On the contrary, It is opposed to a special virtue, namely justice.
I answer that, The term transgression is derived from bodily movement
and applied to moral actions. Now a person is said to transgress in
bodily movement, when he steps [graditur] beyond [trans] a fixed
boundary---and it is a negative precept that fixes the boundary that man
must not exceed in his moral actions. Wherefore to transgress, properly
speaking, is to act against a negative precept.
Now materially considered this may be common to all the species of sin,
because man transgresses a Divine precept by any species of mortal sin.
But if we consider it formally, namely under its special aspect of an act
against a negative precept, it is a special sin in two ways. First, in so
far as it is opposed to those kinds of sin that are opposed to the other
virtues: for just as it belongs properly to legal justice to consider a
precept as binding, so it belongs properly to a transgression to consider
a precept as an object of contempt. Secondly, in so far as it is distinct
from omission which is opposed to an affirmative precept.
Reply to Objection 1: Even as legal justice is "all virtue" (Question [58], Article [5]) as
regards its subject and matter, so legal injustice is materially "all
sin." It is in this way that Ambrose defined sin, considering it from the
point of view of legal injustice.
Reply to Objection 2: The natural inclination concerns the precepts of the
natural law. Again, a laudable custom has the force of a precept; since
as Augustine says in an epistle On the Fast of the Sabbath (Ep. xxxvi),
"a custom of God's people should be looked upon as law." Hence both sin
and transgression may be against a laudable custom and against a natural
inclination.
Reply to Objection 3: All these species of sin may include transgression, if we
consider them not under their proper aspects, but under a special aspect,
as stated above. The sin of omission, however, is altogether distinct
from the sin of transgression.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 79 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that omission is not a special sin. For every sin
is either original or actual. Now omission is not original sin, for it is
not contracted through origin nor is it actual sin, for it may be
altogether without act, as stated above (FS, Question [71], Article [5]) when we were
treating of sins in general. Therefore omission is not a special sin.
Objection 2: Further, every sin is voluntary. Now omission sometimes is not
voluntary but necessary, as when a woman is violated after taking a vow
of virginity, or when one lose that which one is under an obligation to
restore, or when a priest is bound to say Mass, and is prevented from
doing so. Therefore omission is not always a sin.
Objection 3: Further, it is possible to fix the time when any special sin
begins. But this is not possible in the case of omission, since one is
not altered by not doing a thing, no matter when the omission occurs, and
yet the omission is not always sinful. Therefore omission is not a
special sin.
Objection 4: Further, every special sin is opposed to a special virtue. But it
is not possible to assign any special virtue to which omission is
opposed, both because the good of any virtue can be omitted, and because
justice to which it would seem more particularly opposed, always requires
an act, even in declining from evil, as stated above (Article [1], ad 2), while
omission may be altogether without act. Therefore omission is not a
special sin.
On the contrary, It is written (@James 4:17): "To him . . . who knoweth
to do good and doth it not, to him it is sin."
I answer that, omission signifies the non-fulfilment of a good, not
indeed of any good, but of a good that is due. Now good under the aspect
of due belongs properly to justice; to legal justice, if the thing due
depends on Divine or human law; to special justice, if the due is
something in relation to one's neighbor. Wherefore, in the same way as
justice is a special virtue, as stated above (Question [58], Articles [6],7), omission
is a special sin distinct from the sins which are opposed to the other
virtues; and just as doing good, which is the opposite of omitting it, is
a special part of justice, distinct from avoiding evil, to which
transgression is opposed, so too is omission distinct from transgression.
Reply to Objection 2: Omission is not original but actual sin, not as though it
had some act essential to it, but for as much as the negation of an act
is reduced to the genus of act, and in this sense non-action is a kind of
action, as stated above (FS, Question [71], Article [6], ad 1).
Reply to Objection 2: Omission, as stated above, is only of such good as is due
and to which one is bound. Now no man is bound to the impossible:
wherefore no man sins by omission, if he does not do what he cannot.
Accordingly she who is violated after vowing virginity, is guilty of an
omission, not through not having virginity, but through not repenting of
her past sin, or through not doing what she can to fulfil her vow by
observing continence. Again a priest is not bound to say Mass, except he
have a suitable opportunity, and if this be lacking, there is no
omission. And in like manner, a person is bound to restitution, supposing
he has the wherewithal; if he has not and cannot have it, he is not
guilty of an omission, provided he does what he can. The same applies to
other similar cases.
Reply to Objection 3: Just as the sin of transgression is opposed to negative
precepts which regard the avoidance of evil, so the sin of omission is
opposed to affirmative precepts, which regard the doing of good. Now
affirmative precepts bind not for always, but for a fixed time, and at
that time the sin of omission begins. But it may happen that then one is
unable to do what one ought, and if this inability is without any fault
on his part, he does not omit his duty, as stated above (ad 2; FS, Question [71], Article [5]). On the other hand if this inability is due to some previous fault
of his (for instance, if a man gets drunk at night, and cannot get up for
matins, as he ought to), some say that the sin of omission begins when he
engages in an action that is illicit and incompatible with the act to
which he is bound. But this does not seem to be true, for supposing one
were to rouse him by violence and that he went to matins, he would not
omit to go, so that, evidently, the previous drunkenness was not an
omission, but the cause of an omission. Consequently, we must say that
the omission begins to be imputed to him as a sin, when the time comes
for the action; and yet this is on account of a preceding cause by reason
of which the subsequent omission becomes voluntary.
Reply to Objection 4: Omission is directly opposed to justice, as stated above;
because it is a non-fulfilment of a good of virtue, but only under the
aspect of due, which pertains to justice. Now more is required for an act
to be virtuous and meritorious than for it to be sinful and
demeritorious, because "good results from an entire cause, whereas evil
arises from each single defect" [*Dionysius, De Div. Nom. iv]. Wherefore
the merit of justice requires an act, whereas an omission does not.
Index [<< | >>]
Second Part of the Second Part [<< | >>]
Question: 79 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that a sin of omission is more grievous than a sin
of transgression. For "delictum" would seem to signify the same as
"derelictum" [*Augustine, Questions. in Levit., qu. xx], and therefore is
seemingly the same as an omission. But "delictum" denotes a more grievous
offence than transgression, because it deserves more expiation as appears
from Lev. 5. Therefore the sin of omission is more grievous than the sin
of transgression.
Objection 2: Further, the greater evil is opposed to the greater good, as the
Philosopher declares (Ethic. viii, 10). Now to do good is a more
excellent part of justice, than to decline from evil, to which
transgression is opposed, as stated above (Article [1], ad 3). Therefore
omission is a graver sin than transgression.
Objection 3: Further, sins of transgression may be either venial or mortal.
But sins of omission seem to be always mortal, since they are opposed to
an affirmative precept. Therefore omission would seem to be a graver sin
than transgression.
Objection 4: Further, the pain of loss which consists in being deprived of
seeing God and is inflicted for the sin of omission, is a greater
punishment than the pain of sense, which is inflicted for the sin of
transgression, as Chrysostom states (Hom. xxiii super Matth.). Now
punishment is proportionate to fault. Therefore the sin of omission is
graver than the sin of transgression.
On the contrary, It is easier to refrain from evil deeds than to
accomplish good deeds. Therefore it is a graver sin not to refrain from
an evil deed, i.e. "to transgress," than not to accomplish a good deed,
which is "to omit."
I answer that, The gravity of a sin depends on its remoteness from
virtue. Now contrariety is the greatest remoteness, according to Metaph.
x [*Didot. ed. ix, 4]. Wherefore a thing is further removed from its
contrary than from its simple negation; thus black is further removed
from white than not-white is, since every black is not-white, but not
conversely. Now it is evident that transgression is contrary to an act of
virtue, while omission denotes the negation thereof: for instance it is a
sin of omission, if one fail to give one's parents due reverence, while
it is a sin of transgression to revile them or injure them in any way.
Hence it is evident that, simply and absolutely speaking, transgression
is a graver sin than omission, although a particular omission may be
graver than a particular transgression.
Reply to Objection 1: "Delictum" in its widest sense denotes any kind of
omission; but sometimes it is taken strictly for the omission of
something concerning God, or for a man's intentional and as it were
contemptuous dereliction of duty: and then it has a certain gravity, for
which reason it demands a greater expiation.
Reply to Objection 2: The opposite of "doing good" is both "not doing good,"
which is an omission, and "doing evil," which is a transgression: but the
first is opposed by contradiction, the second by contrariety, which
implies greater remoteness: wherefore transgression is the more grievous
sin.
Reply to Objection 3: Just as omission is opposed to affirmative precepts, so is
transgression opposed to negative precepts: wherefore both, strictly
speaking, have the character of mortal sin. Transgression and omission,
however, may be taken broadly for any infringement of an affirmative or
negative precept, disposing to the opposite of such precept: and so
taking both in a broad sense they may be venial sins.
Reply to Objection 4: To the sin of transgression there correspond both the pain
of loss on account of the aversion from God, and the pain of sense, on
account of the inordinate conversion to a mutable good. In like manner
omission deserves not only the pain of loss, but also the pain of sense,
according to Mt. 7:19, "Every tree that bringeth not forth good fruit
shall be cut down, and shall be cast into the fire"; and this on account
of the root from which it grows, although it does not necessarily imply
conversion to any mutable good.