Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
We must now consider the knowledge imprinted or infused in the soul of
Christ, and under this head there are six points of inquiry:
(1) Whether Christ knows all things by this knowledge?
(2) Whether He could use this knowledge by turning to phantasms?
(3) Whether this knowledge was collative?
(4) Of the comparison of this knowledge with the angelic knowledge;
(5) Whether it was a habitual knowledge?
(6) Whether it was distinguished by various habits?
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 1 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that by this knowledge Christ did not know all
things. For this knowledge is imprinted upon Christ for the perfection of
the passive intellect. Now the passive intellect of the human soul does
not seem to be in potentiality to all things simply, but only to those
things with regard to which it can be reduced to act by the active
intellect, which is its proper motor; and these are knowable by natural
reason. Therefore by this knowledge Christ did not know what exceeded the
natural reason.
Objection 2: Further, phantasms are to the human intellect as colors to sight,
as is said De Anima iii, 18,31,39. But it does not pertain to the
perfection of the power of seeing to know what is without color.
Therefore it does not pertain to the perfection of human intellect to
know things of which there are no phantasms, such as separate substances.
Hence, since this knowledge was in Christ for the perfection of His
intellective soul, it seems that by this knowledge He did not know
separate substances.
Objection 3: Further, it does not belong to the perfection of the intellect to
know singulars. Hence it would seem that by this knowledge the soul of
Christ did not know singulars.
On the contrary, It is written (@Is. 11:2) that "the Spirit of wisdom and
understanding, of knowledge and counsel shall fill Him [*Vulg.: 'The
Spirit of the Lord shall rest upon Him, the Spirit of wisdom and
understanding, the Spirit of counsel . . . the Spirit of knowledge . . .
'; cf. Ecclus. 15:5]," under which are included all that may be known;
for the knowledge of all Divine things belongs to wisdom, the knowledge
of all immaterial things to understanding, the knowledge of all
conclusions to knowledge [scientia], the knowledge of all practical
things to counsel. Hence it would seem that by this knowledge Christ had
the knowledge of all things.
I answer that, As was said above (Question [9], Article [1]), it was fitting that the
soul of Christ should be wholly perfected by having each of its powers
reduced to act. Now it must be borne in mind that in the human soul, as
in every creature, there is a double passive power: one in comparison
with a natural agent; the other in comparison with the first agent, which
can reduce any creature to a higher act than a natural agent can reduce
it, and this is usually called the obediential power of a creature. Now
both powers of Christ's soul were reduced to act by this divinely
imprinted knowledge. And hence, by it the soul of Christ knew: First,
whatever can be known by force of a man's active intellect, e.g.
whatever pertains to human sciences; secondly, by this knowledge Christ
knew all things made known to man by Divine revelation, whether they
belong to the gift of wisdom or the gift of prophecy, or any other gift
of the Holy Ghost; since the soul of Christ knew these things more fully
and completely than others. Yet He did not know the Essence of God by
this knowledge, but by the first alone, of which we spoke above (Question [10]).
Reply to Objection 1: This reason refers to the natural power of an intellective
soul in comparison with its natural agent, which is the active intellect.
Reply to Objection 2: The human soul in the state of this life, since it is
somewhat fettered by the body, so as to be unable to understand without
phantasms, cannot understand separate substances. But after the state of
this life the separated soul will be able, in a measure, to know separate
substances by itself, as was said in the FP, Question [89], Articles [1],2, and this is
especially clear as regards the souls of the blessed. Now before His
Passion, Christ was not merely a wayfarer but also a comprehensor; hence
His soul could know separate substances in the same way that a separated
soul could.
Reply to Objection 3: The knowledge of singulars pertains to the perfection of
the intellective soul, not in speculative knowledge, but in practical
knowledge, which is imperfect without the knowledge of singulars, in
which operations exist, as is said Ethic. vi, 7. Hence for prudence are
required the remembrance of past things, knowledge of present things, and
foresight of future things, as Tully says (De Invent. ii). Therefore,
since Christ had the fulness of prudence by the gift of counsel, He
consequently knew all singular things---present, past, and future.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 2 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the soul of Christ could not understand by
this knowledge except by turning to phantasms, because, as is stated De
Anima iii, 18,31,39, phantasms are compared to man's intellective soul as
colors to sight. But Christ's power of seeing could not become actual
save by turning to colors. Therefore His intellective soul could
understand nothing except by turning to phantasms.
Objection 2: Further, Christ's soul is of the same nature as ours. otherwise
He would not be of the same species as we, contrary to what the Apostle
says (@Phil. 2:7) " . . . being made in the likeness of men." But our soul
cannot understand except by turning to phantasms. Hence, neither can
Christ's soul otherwise understand.
Objection 3: Further, senses are given to man to help his intellect. Hence, if
the soul of Christ could understand without turning to phantasms, which
arise in the senses, it would follow that in the soul of Christ the
senses were useless, which is not fitting. Therefore it seems that the
soul of Christ can only understand by turning to phantasms.
On the contrary, The soul of Christ knew certain things which could not
be known by the senses, viz. separate substances. Therefore it could
understand without turning to phantasms.
I answer that, In the state before His Passion Christ was at the same
time a wayfarer and a comprehensor, as will be more clearly shown (Question [15], Article [10]). Especially had He the conditions of a wayfarer on the part of the
body, which was passible; but the conditions of a comprehensor He had
chiefly on the part of the soul. Now this is the condition of the soul of
a comprehensor, viz. that it is nowise subject to its body, or dependent
upon it, but wholly dominates it. Hence after the resurrection glory will
flow from the soul to the body. But the soul of man on earth needs to
turn to phantasms, because it is fettered by the body and in a measure
subject to and dependent upon it. And hence the blessed both before and
after the resurrection can understand without turning to phantasms. And
this must be said of the soul of Christ, which had fully the capabilities
of a comprehensor.
Reply to Objection 1: This likeness which the Philosopher asserts is not with
regard to everything. For it is manifest that the end of the power of
seeing is to know colors; but the end of the intellective power is not to
know phantasms, but to know intelligible species, which it apprehends
from and in phantasms, according to the state of the present life.
Therefore there is a likeness in respect of what both powers regard, but
not in respect of that in which the condition of both powers is
terminated. Now nothing prevents a thing in different states from
reaching its end by different ways: albeit there is never but one proper
end of a thing. Hence, although the sight knows nothing without color;
nevertheless in a certain state the intellect can know without phantasms,
but not without intelligible species.
Reply to Objection 2: Although the soul of Christ was of the same nature as our
souls, yet it had a state which our souls have not yet in fact, but only
in hope, i.e. the state of comprehension.
Reply to Objection 3: Although the soul of Christ could understand without
turning to phantasms, yet it could also understand by turning to
phantasms. Hence the senses were not useless in it; especially as the
senses are not afforded to man solely for intellectual knowledge, but for
the need of animal life.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 3 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that the soul of Christ had not this knowledge by
way of comparison. For Damascene says (De Fide Orth. iii, 14): "We do not
uphold counsel or choice in Christ." Now these things are withheld from
Christ only inasmuch as they imply comparison and discursion. Therefore
it seems that there was no collative or discursive knowledge in Christ.
Objection 2: Further, man needs comparison and discursion of reason in order
to find out the unknown. But the soul of Christ knew everything, as was
said above (Question [10], Article [2]). Hence there was no discursive or collative
knowledge in Him.
Objection 3: Further, the knowledge in Christ's soul was like that of
comprehensors, who are likened to the angels, according to Mt. 22:30. Now
there is no collative or discursive knowledge in the angels, as Dionysius
shows (Div. Nom. vii). Therefore there was no discursive or collative
knowledge in the soul of Christ.
On the contrary, Christ had a rational soul, as was shown (Question [5], Article [4]).
Now the proper operation of a rational soul consists in comparison and
discursion from one thing to another. Therefore there was collative and
discursive knowledge in Christ.
I answer that, Knowledge may be discursive or collative in two ways.
First, in the acquisition of the knowledge, as happens to us, who proceed
from one thing to the knowledge of another, as from causes to effects,
and conversely. And in this way the knowledge in Christ's soul was not
discursive or collative, since this knowledge which we are now
considering was divinely infused, and not acquired by a process of
reasoning. Secondly, knowledge may be called discursive or collative in
use; as at times those who know, reason from cause to effect, not in
order to learn anew, but wishing to use the knowledge they have. And in
this way the knowledge in Christ's soul could be collative or discursive;
since it could conclude one thing from another, as it pleased, as in Mt.
17:24,25, when our Lord asked Peter: "Of whom do the kings of the earth
receive tribute, of their own children, or of strangers?" On Peter
replying: "Of strangers," He concluded: "Then the children are free."
Reply to Objection 1: From Christ is excluded that counsel which is with doubt;
and consequently choice, which essentially includes such counsel; but the
practice of using counsel is not excluded from Christ.
Reply to Objection 2: This reason rests upon discursion and comparison, as used
to acquire knowledge.
Reply to Objection 3: The blessed are likened to the angels in the gifts of
graces; yet there still remains the difference of natures. And hence to
use comparison and discursion is connatural to the souls of the blessed,
but not to angels.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 4 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that this knowledge was not greater in Christ than
in the angels. For perfection is proportioned to the thing perfected. But
the human soul in the order of nature is below the angelic nature.
Therefore since the knowledge we are now speaking of is imprinted upon
Christ's soul for its perfection, it seems that this knowledge is less
than the knowledge by which the angelic nature is perfected.
Objection 2: Further, the knowledge of Christ's soul was in a measure
comparative and discursive, which cannot be said of the angelic
knowledge. Therefore the knowledge of Christ's soul was less than the
knowledge of the angels.
Objection 3: Further, the more immaterial knowledge is, the greater it is. But
the knowledge of the angels is more immaterial than the knowledge of
Christ's soul, since the soul of Christ is the act of a body, and turns
to phantasms, which cannot be said of the angels. Therefore the knowledge
of angels is greater than the knowledge of Christ's soul.
On the contrary, The Apostle says (@Heb. 2:9): "For we see Jesus, Who was
made a little lower than the angels, for the suffering of death, crowned
with glory and honor"; from which it is plain that Christ is said to be
lower than the angels only in regard to the suffering of death. And
hence, not in knowledge.
I answer that, The knowledge imprinted on Christ's soul may be looked at
in two ways: First, as regards what it has from the inflowing cause;
secondly, as regards what it has from the subject receiving it. Now with
regard to the first, the knowledge imprinted upon the soul of Christ was
more excellent than the knowledge of the angels, both in the number of
things known and in the certainty of the knowledge; since the spiritual
light, which is imprinted on the soul of Christ, is much more excellent
than the light which pertains to the angelic nature. But as regards the
second, the knowledge imprinted on the soul of Christ is less than the
angelic knowledge, in the manner of knowing that is natural to the human
soul, i.e. by turning to phantasms, and by comparison and discursion.
And hereby the reply to the objections is made clear.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 5 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that in Christ there was no habitual knowledge. For
it has been said (Question [9], Article [1]) that the highest perfection of knowledge
befitted Christ's soul. But the perfection of an actually existing
knowledge is greater than that of a potentially or habitually existing
knowledge. Therefore it was fitting for Him to know all things actually.
Therefore He had not habitual knowledge.
Objection 2: Further, since habits are ordained to acts, a habitual knowledge
which is never reduced to act would seem useless. Now, since Christ knew
all things, as was said Question [10], Article [2], He could not have considered all
things actually, thinking over one after another, since the infinite
cannot be passed over by enumeration. Therefore the habitual knowledge of
certain things would have been useless to Him---which is unfitting.
Therefore He had an actual and not a habitual knowledge of what He knew.
Objection 3: Further, habitual knowledge is a perfection of the knower. But
perfection is more noble than the thing perfected. If, therefore, in the
soul of Christ there was any created habit of knowledge, it would follow
that this created thing was nobler than the soul of Christ. Therefore
there was no habitual knowledge in Christ's soul.
On the contrary, The knowledge of Christ we are now speaking about was
univocal with our knowledge, even as His soul was of the same species as
ours. But our knowledge is in the genus of habit. Therefore the knowledge
of Christ was habitual.
I answer that, As stated above (Article [4]), the mode of the knowledge
impressed on the soul of Christ befitted the subject receiving it. For
the received is in the recipient after the mode of the recipient. Now the
connatural mode of the human soul is that it should understand sometimes
actually, and sometimes potentially. But the medium between a pure power
and a completed act is a habit: and extremes and medium are of the same
genus. Thus it is plain that it is the connatural mode of the human soul
to receive knowledge as a habit. Hence it must be said that the knowledge
imprinted on the soul of Christ was habitual, for He could use it when He
pleased.
Reply to Objection 1: In Christ's soul there was a twofold knowledge---each most
perfect of its kind: the first exceeding the mode of human nature, as by
it He saw the Essence of God, and other things in It, and this was the
most perfect, simply. Nor was this knowledge habitual, but actual with
respect to everything He knew in this way. But the second knowledge was
in Christ in a manner proportioned to human nature, i.e. inasmuch as He
knew things by species divinely imprinted upon Him, and of this knowledge
we are now speaking. Now this knowledge was not most perfect, simply, but
merely in the genus of human knowledge; hence it did not behoove it to be
always in act.
Reply to Objection 2: Habits are reduced to act by the command of the will, since
a habit is that "with which we act when we wish." Now the will is
indeterminate in regard to infinite things. Yet it is not useless, even
when it does not actually tend to all; provided it actually tends to
everything in fitting place and time. And hence neither is a habit
useless, even if all that it extends to is not reduced to act; provided
that that which befits the due end of the will be reduced to act
according as the matter in hand and the time require.
Reply to Objection 3: Goodness and being are taken in two ways: First, simply;
and thus a substance, which subsists in its being and goodness, is a good
and a being; secondly, being and goodness are taken relatively, and in
this way an accident is a being and a good, not that it has being and
goodness, but that its subject is a being and a good. And hence habitual
knowledge is not simply better or more excellent than the soul of Christ;
but relatively, since the whole goodness of habitual knowledge is added
to the goodness of the subject.
Index [<< | >>]
Third Part [<< | >>]
Question: 11 [<< | >>]
Article: 6 [<< | >>]
Objection 1: It would seem that in the soul of Christ there was only one habit
of knowledge. For the more perfect knowledge is, the more united it is;
hence the higher angels understand by the more universal forms, as was
said in the FP, Question [55], Article [3]. Now Christ's knowledge was most perfect.
Therefore it was most one. Therefore it was not distinguished by several
habits.
Objection 2: Further, our faith is derived from Christ's knowledge; hence it
is written (@Heb. 12:2): "Looking on Jesus the author and finisher of
faith." But there is only one habit of faith about all things believed,
as was said in the SS, Question [4], Article [6]. Much more, therefore, was there only
one habit of knowledge in Christ.
Objection 3: Further, knowledge is distinguished by the divers formalities of
knowable things. But the soul of Christ knew everything under one
formality, i.e. by a divinely infused light. Therefore in Christ there
was only one habit of knowledge.
On the contrary, It is written (Zach. 3:9) that on "one" stone, i.e.
Christ, "there are seven eyes." Now by the eye is understood knowledge.
Therefore it would seem that in Christ there were several habits of
knowledge.
I answer that, As stated above (Articles [4],5), the knowledge imprinted on
Christ's soul has a mode connatural to a human soul. Now it is connatural
to a human soul to receive species of a lesser universality than the
angels receive; so that it knows different specific natures by different
intelligible species. But it so happens that we have different habits of
knowledge, because there are different classes of knowable things,
inasmuch as what are in one genus are known by one habit; thus it is said
(Poster. i, 42) that "one science is of one class of object." And hence
the knowledge imprinted on Christ's soul was distinguished by different
habits.
Reply to Objection 1: As was said (Article [4]), the knowledge of Christ's soul is most perfect, and exceeds the knowledge of angels with regard to what is in it on the part of God's gift; but it is below the angelic knowledge as regards the mode of the recipient. And it pertains to this mode that this knowledge is distinguished by various habits, inasmuch as it regards more particular species.
Reply to Objection 2: Our faith rests upon the First Truth; and hence Christ is
the author of our faith by the Divine knowledge, which is simply one.
Reply to Objection 3: The divinely infused light is the common formality for
understanding what is divinely revealed, as the light of the active
intellect is with regard to what is naturally known. Hence, in the soul
of Christ there must be the proper species of singular things, in order
to know each with proper knowledge; and in this way there must be divers
habits of knowledge in Christ's soul, as stated above.